“It can create workplace harassment that is both illegal and damaging to morale.”
This article has thus far positioned the University, admittedly somewhat myopically, as principally a place of employment, not just for student employees but also for the faculty and staff that travel everyday to work within Middletown’s ivory tower. As a place of employment, it is of the utmost importance to address issues of harassment that can occur—and have indeed occurred in the past—as a result of chalking.

Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 (42 U.S.C. §2000e-2(a)(1)) asserts that it is “an unlawful employment practice for an employer…to discriminate against any individual with respect to his compensation, terms, conditions, or privileges of employment, because of such individual’s race, color, religion, sex, or national origin.” (The list of protected categories has subsequently been expanded through later legislation.) In Meritor Savings Bank v. Vinson (1986), the Court further determined that Title VII is violated when a workplace is composed of “discriminatory intimidation, ridicule, and insult”—i.e. harassment—in a way that is “sufficiently severe or pervasive to alter the conditions of the victim’s employment and create an abusive working environment.”

This means that the University may be financially liable to employee exposure to myriad forms of harassment. When exploring employer liability for coworker and non-employee harassment, the Court in Faragher v. City of Boca Raton (1998) repeatedly referenced 29 C.F.R. §1604.11, which deals with a “sexual harassment hostile environment” specifically. This legislation holds in (d) that “with respect to conduct between fellow employees, an employer is responsible for acts of sexual harassment in the workplace where the employer…knows or should have known of the conduct, unless it can show that it took immediate and appropriate corrective action” and in (e) that “an employer may also be responsible for the acts of non-employees…where the employer knows or should have known of the conduct and fails to take immediate and appropriate corrective action.”

Thus, the University is responsible for protecting employees from obscene pornography, racial epithets, etc., regardless of where they originate, because, in failing to respond, it is condoning a hostile work environment. A “hostile” environment, the Court explains, can be ascertained through a “reasonable person” looking into the circumstances of the conduct, including “the frequency of the discriminatory conduct; its severity; whether it is physically threatening or humiliating, or a mere offensive utterance; and whether it unreasonably interferes with an employee’s work performance.” Harris v. Forklift Systems, Inc. (1993).

In a final note: Title VII protections are “based on the cumulative effects of individual acts.” National R.R. Passenger Corp. v. Morgan (2002). Thus, one isolated action—one sexually explicit chalking, for example—is not at question, but rather the University’s systematic response.

It is without question an admirable goal for the University to maintain a safe and inclusive working environment, and more admirable still to desire to go above and beyond minimum legal requirements to achieve this goal. However, both objectives could still be fulfilled without a chalking proscription; equally legally protectable speech is able to coexist with workplace safety and inclusivity.

To begin, it has already been noted above that there are several categories of speech that are unprotected, including categories such as obscenity and hate speech that would create the hostile work environment that the University is legally obliged to prevent. Thus, allowing for even a broad protection of speech would not include the speech that is at issue under Title VII. The University must argue, then, that chalking—perhaps as anonymous speech—allows for such unprotected, harassing speech to proliferate so rampantly that the only way to stamp out such hate is to ban the medium altogether. This argument, however, appears not only to be empirically unquantifiable (how would one determine whether one form of speech is per se more harassing than another?) but also, as noted above with Talley, a potentially constitutionally pointless exercise, given that the case seems to suggest that the ability to use punishment as a tool for further prevention is not a sufficient justification to stamp out anonymous speech altogether.

Furthermore, the University’s current policy suggests that chalking that is obscene, discriminatory, etc. will receive more discipline. As noted above, currently a chalker would be brought up on violating CNAC §15; however, chalking that amounts to harassment would also implicate §2 “Harassment and Abuse”. Thus, there would still be recourse under CNAC to prosecute hate speech and obscenity if the moratorium was lifted, and chalking no longer violated §15. CNAC §2 would cover issues of harassment for nefarious chalkers who are caught.

But what about the (vast majority of) chalkings in which no culprit can be determined? Reading Talley together with Morgan and Faragher, the University is responsible under Title VII for how it systematically responds to harassing chalking.

In resident advisor training, student staff are taught that the first step in responding to an instance of hate speech is to cover the text and then call Public Safety so that it can be photographed for evidence and then removed. The privileged position of hiding the speech emphasizes the fact that removal of the speech from the public eye takes immediate precedent, according to University policy; secondary is seeking out responsibility and punishment. Removal of the speech and investigation into responsibility appear to fulfill Morgan’s requirement for employer action—it does not fall to the wayside simply because anonymity decreases the probability of an investigation being fruitful. We do not ban whiteboards from hallways because of the poorly-drawn penises or discriminatory remarks that could be written on them; we do not ban all writing in snow because of the hate speech that has resulted this year alone.

In this way, the argument that insufficient opportunities for punishment requires a wholesale proscription on a form of speech under Title VII does not appear valid, and the University will meet its legal obligation so long as its policy for dealing with any form of hate speech is applied with equal weight to chalking.

However, it is also important here that we do not conflate “legal” with “ethical”—again, we should commend the University for attempting to go above and beyond legal minimums. Indeed, even if the University has a swift response to all obscene and hate speech it finds, this does not account for the emotional ramifications on the few who will inevitably view it before it is removed. And to this we must be sympathetic. However, the danger of undesired speech comes with any medium of speaking, and we must also make sure that the University does not conflate its desire to shield faculty, staff, and students from such hate with its desire to discipline those responsible. An increase in the difficulty of disciplining those responsible as a result of chalk’s anonymity does not transfer to an increase in the difficulty of removing such speech. We must, as a community, condemn hateful speech when we see it, but—on both legal and ethical grounds—we also must not banish everyone into silence as a result of fear. 

In the end, so long as the University polices chalking in the same way that it polices its bulletin boards, hallways, and banners, there is nothing to suggest that chalking would itself violate Title VII and thus create workplace harassment. As a result, the argument is insufficient to justify such a ban.

“It gives many visitors the impression that Wesleyan lacks high intellectual standards and contributes to the sense that the campus is unkempt.”
This is perhaps the most difficult pill to swallow as an institutional justification for proscribing chalking. However, it is also the justification listed in the Student Handbook for the chalking ban: the University states that it wishes to “protect freedom of expression while encouraging respect for University property and the appearance of the campus.” Given that the handbook provides only basic guidelines for other (oftentimes anonymous) speech such as posters and banners, the University, by banning chalking wholesale, is therefore suggesting that chalking is so drastically per se disrespectful and aesthetically displeasing that it can be proscribed at whim.

First, let us consider the appearance argument. To begin, sidewalks alongside public roads are considered city property, and therefore the chalking ban does not apply. Tour groups often use these sidewalks in their elliptical route and can therefore still be exposed to such “unkempt” scribblings despite the ban. It would be spurious at best to suggest that the University will be able to maintain a pristine appearance by enacting a ban on chalking given the public sidewalks that run like rivers through campus.

Further, it would be well within the University’s rights to enact time, place, and manner (TPM) restrictions on chalking. Renton v. Playtime Theatres (1986). For example, it can proscribe chalking on the sides of buildings or over informational content on pavement (such as handicapped parking symbols or painted text like “EMERGENCY LANE”). This would help control the “unkempt” appearance that would occur from chalking much more effectively while still allowing for protectable speech to survive. That is, unless the administration is to assume that students will chalk political messages across all campus without regard to legibility, piling one top of another and causing an incomprehensible pandemonium of colored calcite.

TPM restrictions on chalking would also provide a less restrictive means of dealing with concerns of respect. Chalk, unlike paint and marker, is a transient form of communication, and therefore any presumed disrespect in this argument seems to derive principally from the act of chalking rather than the content. While concerns of respect would be valid for chalking on sides of buildings or over informational content, it is much more difficult to suggest that all chalking is by its nature improperly disrespectful. Followed to its logical conclusion, would this not suggest that all forms of dissent—protest signs, petitions, chants—are similarly disrespectful? In terms of respect, what is the difference between a student holding a protest sign with “Michael Roth, what are you doing about global warming” and having those same words emblazoned with chalk? Unless we are ready to lambaste all forms of political dissent as proscribable disrespect, we must accept that concerns of respect result from the time, place, and manner of the chalking, and not chalking per se as a medium of communication.

There is also little argument that chalking could be disrespectful because it damages University property. Admittedly, conservation of property is a compelling interest that can, at times, limit speech. Clark v. Community for Creative Non-Violence (1984). This is especially true for private (as opposed to government) property. However, chalking does not amount to damage to property—it is an impermanent form of communication that can easily be removed. Let us even assume, for the sake of argument, that certain surfaces could be irreparably damaged by chalk; again, TPM restrictions would take care of the issue without creating an overbroad policy. Thus, there is no evidence to suggest that chalking is disrespectful by its very nature in a way that can allow for its control.

The gravest concern about this argument—both in terms of appearance and in terms of respect—is that it provides little possibility for students to have any control over the space in which they live. What seems to underscore this argument is the idea that the University exists as a showroom for prospective consumers of our educational product, and students should not be granted allowance to make the space in which they are forced to live for four years appear in any way a lived space. While aesthetic value may be a compelling interest in the foregrounds of the White House, Mahoney v. Doe (2011), it makes strikingly little sense in the context of the University.

Given the WestCo courtyard project and the ability to hang fliers on billboards and kiosks throughout campus under only basic civility guidelines, the chalking ban as aesthetic preservation appears to be drastically inconsistent with current University policy. It would therefore be disturbingly upsetting for the University to take seriously the argument that it must proscribe chalking in order to preserve the campus. The aesthetic “beauty” of a sterile campus should not be considered a sufficiently compelling interest for the ban given the plethora of less restrictive options to accomplish this goal, nor should we accept the conflation of squashing dissent with upholding standards of respect.

Next Page

Pages: 1 2 3 4 5

  • Jacon Mayer ’10

    Nice article Eric.

    Unfortunately, what you don’t address is the contract Wesleyan forces students to sign: the Code of Non-Academic Conduct. The code is riddled with broad language that essentially grants the University the power to do whatever it wants, and students are then contractually bound to let them. There are any number of clauses in the CNAC that would be illegal as policies, but as a contract are perfectly legal. Since you clearly enjoy legal research, I’d love to see an article that expounds on those flaws in the CNAC. In my mind this is but one example of how the University abuses its position of power to infringe on students’ rights as citizens of the United States, residents of CT, and (this is more rare, I’ll grant) as human beings.

    • Eric Stephen

      Hi Jacon,

      Thank you for your comment !

      I think you raise a good point, and admittedly I don’t know much about contract law. I think I would need to look more into the language and logic of CNAC when students pledge to it before I say anything concrete. However, here are some thoughts:

      First I would want to question whether this could really be considered an “employment contract”. I do not dispute that employment contracts can limit the First Amendment rights of employees, but I am wondering if CNAC has anything built in that’s actually about employment (vs. student life). Many students come to Wes and get campus jobs, many students don’t. And many people who work for the University are not students under CNAC. To say that a pledge everyone takes when coming to Wesleyan, even those who never intend to or never do get a campus job, is an employment contract seems illogical. It seems like the contract would be presented when you actually apply for a campus job (maybe when you fill out your W-4 ??). To me, it seems like what your referring to would be much closer to the community contract my grandparents signed when the moved into a retirement community than an actual employment contract, and so it may be difficult for the University to argue it should be read so expansively.

      But assuming my sophomoric understanding of contracts is wrong and what your referring to actually can be seen as an employment contract — from what I understand, state employment statutes can still provide relief. State employment statutes wouldn’t have any teeth if any employer can just say “in order to get this job you have to sign this contract that accepts that we are above the law, including laws that explicitly protect you as an employee from me”. I believe that any employment contract must be made with current employment statutes in mind, including sec. 31-51q above.

      But I think what you’re getting at is the broader question of what happens when someone wears the hat of student (no speech rights) and also the hat of employee (some speech rights) when the two are in tension. I would argue that the University should not think it can disregard student employee rights just because it also plays landlord and educator on top of employer, which I touch on a little bit in the Argus article.

      These are just my first thoughts, and this is definitely something I will look into, so thank you for bringing it up. Maybe others reading this will know more than me here too? I hope my first thoughts may be useful though in the meantime.

      • wesalum ’78

        It seems that what most fail to appreciate is that this is not a speech issue, but a property rights issue. Each of the surfaces that were routinely used for chalking are private property. The trustees of the University who hold this property in public trust and the employees whom they designate to execute the public trust have broad latitude as to how they choose to use property in furthering the mission. At no time in the past ten years, have I seen the administration or Trustees attempt to restrict the speech of the students. Any restriction have always been with respect to the use of University property. Surely, Wesleyan students remain creative enough to share their message in a way that reaches the intended audience and is constitutionally protected.
        Finally, the University has never outlawed chalking. They have just communicated the consequences for defacing University property. Free choice remains as to whether the message is worth the consequences.

      • wesalum ’78

        It seems that what most fail to appreciate is that this is not a speech issue, but a property rights issue. Each of the surfaces that were routinely used for chalking are private property. The trustees of the University who hold this property in public trust and the employees whom they designate to execute the public trust have broad latitude as to how they choose to use property in furthering the mission. At no time in the past ten years, have I seen the administration or Trustees attempt to restrict the speech of the students. Any restriction have always been with respect to the use of University property. Surely, Wesleyan students remain creative enough to share their message in a way that reaches the intended audience and is constitutionally protected.
        Finally, the University has never outlawed chalking. They have just communicated the consequences for defacing University property. Free choice remains as to whether the message is worth the consequences.

  • Melody Moezzi

    Thanks for this. I’m an alum (2001), and the reason I chose Wesleyan (my “safety”) after getting accepted to other, more well-known universities was because the day I stepped on campus for a visit, I saw a chalking that read, “Keep your laws off my cunt.” At that moment, I knew Wes was for me, and I was right. It had nothing to do with the shock factor or even the political position of the chalking. It was because of the mere fact that this was a place where you could speak your mind freely, where people knew how to use language as a weapon and weren’t afraid to do it. I’m sad to hear that y’all don’t have the same freedoms we did, but I’m happy to see that we still have sharp minds willing to fight for what’s right. Bravo Eric!

    • My “safety?” What a way to both brag and knock your fellow classmates at the same time. By no means is Wesleyan considered a safety school, and to say so insults the achievement of those who got in who considered Wesleyan a reach.

  • Lee Jacobson ’05

    I was a student at the time this occurred. I was told by the student body president at the time that the Aramark cafeteria workers were threatening to sue the school for sexual harassment in the workplace based on sexual and extremely graphic chalkings throughout campus. One chalking that sticks was written outside Foss 10 (next to admissions) on revisit weekend, “I’m going to fuck your son in the ass then make him suck my dick and taste his ass on my dick.” I can assure you, that while most chalkings were tamer, that one was by no means uniquely sexual. President Bennett gracefully decided to take the flack for the chalking moratorium by himself, and not expose the campus workers to the abuse that they would undoubtedly have received from the student body. The student body was unresponsive to several pleas to reduce the graphic sexual content in the chalk messages and the moratorium was a result. Certainly an entire group of employees feeling sexually harassed is of “public concern?”

    • Eric Stephen

      Hi Lee,

      Thank you for your comment.

      In the article on page 4 I take up the possibility of “sexual harrastment hostile environment” at length, concluding that ” so long as the University polices chalking in the same way that it polices its bulletin boards, hallways, and banners, there is nothing to suggest that chalking would itself violate Title VII and thus create workplace harassment.” What may also be helpful is paragraphs 4 – 10 on page 3. I would argue that dozens of lower court cases would suggest that the quote you gave above would be considered obscenity under Miller, and hence not protected. The University has a legal responsibility to respond to such unprotected statements or drawings that foster SHHE, but the doctrine of overbreadth suggests that it cannot proscribe protectable speech in the process of doing this (Page 2). This is what is at issue. I am not suggesting some sort of free speech absolutism where students can write threats, libel, hate speech, etc. without any problem — only that the ban as it exists is questionably overbroad because less restrictive means can be used to further the same ends.

  • This is interesting. It reminds me of a local incident here in LA. I was very involved with Occupy LA, and we had a big brouhaha over chalking. People were cited for chalking on public sidewalks even though it is considered protected speech. Mayor Villaraigosa and the Chief of Police had a press conference in which they said that they had passed a city wide ordinance against it, which even the local reporters had to question the legality of. Occupy media people did some research and a video of the same mayor telling the Livestrong people they could chalk their message throughout the city, and even closed down public streets for the event. The video we made of that contrast was striking. They accepted and even encouraged chalking when it was corporate speech. Then Occupy went to the monthly downtown art walk with chalk and fliers about what happened to Occupiers. And regular art walk goers, many of whom were parents with children, became incensed and starting chalking messages on the sidewalk. Police were called, and arrests were made. Occupy activists left for another event. People came out of bars and restaurants and saw half the LAPD in riot gear blocking an entire street. Someone threw a rock. And a melee ensued. Of course Occupy was blamed for it even though they weren’t even there at the time.

Twitter